IniciGrupsConversesMésTendències
Cerca al lloc
Aquest lloc utilitza galetes per a oferir els nostres serveis, millorar el desenvolupament, per a anàlisis i (si no has iniciat la sessió) per a publicitat. Utilitzant LibraryThing acceptes que has llegit i entès els nostres Termes de servei i política de privacitat. L'ús que facis del lloc i dels seus serveis està subjecte a aquestes polítiques i termes.

Resultats de Google Books

Clica una miniatura per anar a Google Books.

S'està carregant…

Graham Harman: The Third Table (100 Notes-100 Thoughts Documenta 13)

de Graham Harman

Sèrie: 100 Notes, 100 Thoughts (No. 085)

MembresRessenyesPopularitatValoració mitjanaConverses
911,986,042 (3)Cap
Philosopher Graham Harman repeats Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington's allegory from 1927 of the "two tables": the familiar "table of everyday life" and its rival, the "scientific table" as described by physics. Both are for Harman the results of reductionism and the traditional dichotomy of natural science and humanities. The third and only "real" table belongs to the "third culture," a culture of art that creates objects, and whose purpose is the comprehension that one cannot understand reality but can only love it. The notebook "The Third Table" introduces the philosophy of speculative realism and alludes to the chance to reanimate philosophy in its original sense of philosophia--the love of science. Graham Harman (*1968) is Professor of Philosophy at the American University in Cairo.… (més)
Cap
S'està carregant…

Apunta't a LibraryThing per saber si aquest llibre et pot agradar.

No hi ha cap discussió a Converses sobre aquesta obra.

Graham Harman has just published this concise overview of some of the central themes of his object-oriented philosophy, in a bilingual English-German edition: THE THIRD TABLE (Hatje Cantz Verlag, 2012). The English text occupies just eleven and a half pages (p4-15). The content is quite engaging as he manages to expound his ideas in the form of a response to Sir Arthur Eddington’s famous two table argument, which can be found in his book THE NATURE OF THE PHYSICAL WORLD (available as a free download here), first published in 1928. This allows him to couch his arguments in terms of a running engagement with reductionism, in what Harman sees as its humanistic and scientistic forms. So far so good. Problems arise however when we consider his account of each of Eddington's two tables.
1) THE FIRST TABLE: On Analogical Typology
THE THIRD TABLE does not give us a close reading of Eddington’s 1928 “Introduction”, nor does it intend to. It’s stake lies elsewhere, in a typological reading. From the “Introduction” Harman extracts two types, the everyday table and the scientific one, and he immediately puts them in parallel with C.P. Snow’s two cultures, the sciences and the humanities, “distinguishing”, according to Harman (p5), “so-called literary intellectuals from natural scientists”. (One may ask why the literary intellectuals merit the appellation “so-called”, but not the natural scientists. There would seem to be a residue of scientism that creeps into Harman’s exposition from time to time, even when he is describing his two adversaries).

This is a bold leap of the analogical imagination, but unfortunately in this case it leads him astray. For the everyday table is not the table of the humanities (whatever that is!). For example, Proust’s table, a locus of intense and meaningful events, is not the everyday table. I am obliged here to hypothesise that literature belongs to the humanities, as Harman distinguishes the humanities from the arts, which are capable of rising to, or descending to (depending on your starting point), the Harmanian table, the “only real” table. He further complicates the matter by talking about the table being reducible “upward to a series of effects on people and other things” (p6). Now this is most strange, as Eddington insists on the substantiality of the everyday table, its solidity and compaction. The familiar table is all of a piece, and certainly not a “series of effects”, even less a series of “table-effects on humans” (p7). So the first table, the familiar one, is a blur between the everyday table, the table of the humanities, and the “series of effects” – with Harman sliding glibly from one to the other as if it were all the same to him. What seems to guide some of the slippage is the needs of the analogical argument, now favorising one term in the typological couple, now another. But a basic incertitude reigns as to the identity of the first table, at least in Harman’s text (for Eddington, as we have seen, there is no uncertainty).

Harman has a real architectonic ambition, and, if only for this, he deserves our admiration and encouragement. But the typological imagination, with its bold analogical heuristics, can sometimes play tricks on even the best of us.
2) THE SECOND TABLE: On Reduction
The problem is that Harman seems to have no clear idea of what reduction is. In effect, he presents us with an epistemological straw man supposed to exemplify the reductionism of modern physics. While ostensibly talking about Eddington’s parable of the two tables, Harman condemns the procedure of the “scientist” who, according to him, “reduces the table downward to tiny particles invisible to the eye” (THE THIRD TABLE, p6), “dissolved into rushing electric charges and other tiny elements”. He contrasts this obviously unsatisfactory procedure of reduction with the OOP’s respect for “the autonomous reality” of the table “over and above its causal components” (p7-8). He informs us that the table is an emergent whole which “has features that its various component particles do not have in isolation” (p7).

This is an important point to make, but certainly not to Eddington or to any other physicist worthy of the name. Perhaps Harman is thinking in fact of Badiou and his set-theoretic reductionism, as he further declares that “objects are not just sets of atoms” (p8). However, for any real physicist a table is an emergent structure of particles and fields of force (not just electromagnetic but also gravitational and those of the weak and strong forces) and space-time. Even Eddington speaks of the table as composed of “space pervaded … by fields of force”, “electric charges rushing about with great speed”. Harman is wrong, in my opinion, to treat these “electric charges” as if they were just particles, and he pays no attention to the mention of speed. True, Eddington does talk as well of “electric particles”, but there is a progression in the text over the notion of these particles, from which he first removes all substance (p.xvi), and which he then terms “nuclei of electric force” (p.xvii), to finally declare the notion of a particle, such as an electron, too coloured by concretistic picture thinking and needing to be replaced by mathematical symbolism:

“I can well understand that the younger minds are finding these pictures too concrete and are striving to construct the world out of Hamiltonian functions and symbols so far removed from human preconception that they do not even obey the laws of orthodox arithmetic” (p.xviii).

Thus, contrary to what Harman asserts, there is no “reduction to tiny particles”, but a redescription in terms of a complex, emergent, structure of forces and fields and regions of space-time.

I think Harman confuses reduction between different worlds with reduction inside a particular world. If scientists declared that the physicist’s table was the only real table, as Harman does with his philosophical table (he calls his third table, which can neither be known nor touched, “the only real one”) then that would be a form of reductionism. But we have seen that there is no reduction of the table to a set of tiny particles (how big is a field of force? how far does it extend? Harman is so obsessed with refuting a non-existent particle-reductionism that he does not consider these questions, and goes on to protest against an imaginary “prejudice” that maintains that “only the smallest things are real” (p8). This is precisely the picture-thinking that Eddington is eager to dispel in the physicist’s world). There is no “disintegrating” of the table into nothing but tiny electric charges or material flickerings” (p10). There is no “scientific dissolution” (p8) of the table into its component atoms, as this would be merely be bad science. To this extent, Harman’s new object-oriented ontology is just bad epistemology. ( )
1 vota TBlake | May 18, 2012 |
Sense ressenyes | afegeix-hi una ressenya

Pertany a aquestes sèries

Has d'iniciar sessió per poder modificar les dades del coneixement compartit.
Si et cal més ajuda, mira la pàgina d'ajuda del coneixement compartit.
Títol normalitzat
Títol original
Títols alternatius
Data original de publicació
Gent/Personatges
Llocs importants
Esdeveniments importants
Pel·lícules relacionades
Epígraf
Dedicatòria
Primeres paraules
Citacions
Darreres paraules
Nota de desambiguació
Editor de l'editorial
Creadors de notes promocionals a la coberta
Llengua original
CDD/SMD canònics
LCC canònic

Referències a aquesta obra en fonts externes.

Wikipedia en anglès

Cap

Philosopher Graham Harman repeats Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington's allegory from 1927 of the "two tables": the familiar "table of everyday life" and its rival, the "scientific table" as described by physics. Both are for Harman the results of reductionism and the traditional dichotomy of natural science and humanities. The third and only "real" table belongs to the "third culture," a culture of art that creates objects, and whose purpose is the comprehension that one cannot understand reality but can only love it. The notebook "The Third Table" introduces the philosophy of speculative realism and alludes to the chance to reanimate philosophy in its original sense of philosophia--the love of science. Graham Harman (*1968) is Professor of Philosophy at the American University in Cairo.

No s'han trobat descripcions de biblioteca.

Descripció del llibre
Sumari haiku

Debats actuals

Cap

Cobertes populars

Dreceres

Gèneres

LCC (Clas. Bibl. Congrés EUA)

Valoració

Mitjana: (3)
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3 1
3.5
4
4.5
5

Ets tu?

Fes-te Autor del LibraryThing.

 

Quant a | Contacte | LibraryThing.com | Privadesa/Condicions | Ajuda/PMF | Blog | Botiga | APIs | TinyCat | Biblioteques llegades | Crítics Matiners | Coneixement comú | 204,441,327 llibres! | Barra superior: Sempre visible